Stevens, Katharina

Associate Professor

Philosophy Department

Phone
(403) 329-2159
Fax
(403) 329-5109
Email
katharina.stevens@uleth.ca

About Me

My research interests are in argumentation theory, the ethics of argumentation and legal philosophy. In legal philosophy, I have written and presented on reasoning by precedent and constitutional interpretation. In argumentation theory, I have written on argument by analogy, argument design, virtue argumentation and the ethics of arguing. At the moment, I am finishing a monograph on the ethics of arguing.

I am holding a BoGRC Tier II, researching the Ethics of Argumentation, and I am the co-editor in chief of the Argumentation Theory journal Informal Logic.

If you want to talk about Argumentation Theory or Legal Philosophy - or about philosophy in general - just walk by my office, or send me an email.

Publications

If there are any publications on my CV that you would like to read, and that you do not have access to, send me an email, I am happy to share them.

"The Roles We Make Others Take - Thoughts on the Ethics of Arguing", 2019, TOPOI

Feminist argumentation theorists have criticized the Dominant Adversarial Model in argumentation, according to which arguers should take proponent and opponent roles and argue against one another. The model is deficient because it creates disadvantages for feminine gendered persons in a way that causes significant epistemic and practical harms. In this paper, I argue that the problem that these critics have pointed out can be generalized: whenever an arguer is given a role in the argument the associated tasks and norms of which she cannot fulfill, she is liable to suffer morally significant harms. One way to react to this problem is by requiring arguers to set up argument structures and allocate roles so that the argument will be reasons-reflective in as balanced a way as possible. However, I argue that this would create to heavy a burden. Arguers would then habitually have to take on roles that require them to divert time and energy away from the goals that they started arguing for and instead serve the goal of ideal reasons-reflectiveness. At least prima facie arguers should be able to legitimately devote their time and energy towards their own goals. This creates a problem: On the one hand, structures that create morally significant harms for some arguers should be avoided—on the other hand, arguers should be able to take argument-roles that allow them to devote themselves to their own argumentative goals. Fulfilling the second requirement for some arguers will often create the morally significant harms for their interlocutors. There are two possible solutions for this problem: first, arguers might be required to reach free, consensual agreements on the structure they will adopt for their argument and the way they will distribute argumentative roles. I reject this option as both fundamentally unfeasible and practically unrealistic, based on arguments developed by theorists like Krabbe and Jacobs. I argue that instead, we should take a liberal view on argument ethics. Arguers should abide by moral side constraints to their role taking. They should feel free to take roles that will allow them to concentrate on their argumentative goals, but only if this does not create a situation in which their interlocutors are pushed into a role that that they cannot effectively play.

https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-019-09659-0



"Reasoning By Precedent: Between Rules and Analogies", 2018, Legal Theory:

Abstract: This paper investigates the process of reasoning through which a judge determines whether a precedent-case gives her a binding reason to follow in her present-case. I review the objections that have been raised against the two main accounts of reasoning by precedent: the rule-account and the analogy-account. I argue that both accounts can be made viable by amending them to meet the objections.
Nonetheless, I believe that there is an argument for preferring accounts that integrate analogical reasoning: any account of reasoning by precedent that is descriptively minimally adequate will leave some room for judicial discretion. Discretion should be used under consideration of the best legally relevant arguments for and against a decision. Integrating analogical reasoning helps the judge to bring to her own attention the strongest case for following. Analogical reasoning also eases the recognition of possible reasons for distinguishing. Thereby, it facilitates a more balanced decision-making process.

https://www.cambridge.org/core/services/aop-cambridge-core/content/view/E1E0AF29EAC9A98D98D4EDF7AACEC311/S1352325218000113a.pdf/reasoning_by_precedentbetween_rules_and_analogies.pdf




For other publications, see my CV

and

If you want to read any of my work that is not or not easily accessible, please just email me the title of the paper you are interested in.

In The Media

If you want to read an interview with me, look here:

https://legalphi.wordpress.com/2018/02/09/katharina-stevens/

If you want to watch me give a talk for a non-academic audience, look here:

https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=RbPVLKM6YYg

If you want to know what is going on in the Philosophy-Department in Lethbridge in
general, read our blog:

https://uoflphilosophydepartmentblog.wordpress.com/

If you are interested in the Ethics of Argumentation and would like to watch talks on the topic, here is a speaker series I am organizing:

https://www.argnet.org/ethics-of-arg